I've spent about six weeks now unfolding a philosophical perspective that humanity will evolve, and we will eventually come to a condition of universal peace. I've also carefully inserted the notion that it is within our collective power to hasten that eventuality. Indeed, that being the premise, it becomes our collective duty to hasten universal peace..
Now how do we go about the business of peacemaking? Shall we all find a stage and act as if we've won a beauty contest, and say that we pray for world peace? If you have access to an audience, and feel inspired to do so, I encourage your sentiment, but I'm skeptical that you will accomplish much.
What is needed is a disciplined, organized approach. Specifically, a group working for peace should have good statistical knowledge of the society they wish to act upon, and the obstacles to peace which are presented. The group must develop a plan with acheivable and measurable objectives, and monitor progress, thereby developing a process which will drive improvements in the peaceful actions of that society. When the objectives are met, they should be reviewed, the processes continously improved via statistical control.
If you've been reading along in my posts, this activity sounds like nothing I have said so far. If you've been involved in peace movements in the past it probably sounds unfamiliar as well. This isn't a call for building an enormous rally in a city park and chanting slogans. In fact, it sounds like dreadfully dull, uninspired stuff. Happily, while it sounds like a dreadful process, it will simply manifest as a set of actions which will be oriented toward acheivable goals and pointed toward an ever improving peace dynamic. It will have dull bits, because it entails some hard work and some statistical work, but it will be uplifting and inspiring work as goals are met.
This sounds so utterly foreign to traditional peace organizing because it is, in fact, business theory. I had the pleasure of spending several years at a small but prominent business school, where I was introduced to the theories of W. Edwards Deming, a well-known statististicial and business innovator, who advocated a statistically driven continuous improvement method, which revolutionized several industries. In the years since I completed my studies there, I have come to realize that his model can be almost universally applied to human endeavors. Peacemaking, I believe, is especially well-suited to the model. Apparently Dr. Deming also felt this way; shortly before his death, he formed the Deming Institiute, dedicated to innovations for commerce, prosperity and peace.
One of the hard things about approaching peace with anything like a statistical approach is that we commonly see peace, and peacemaking as a 'fuzzy' concept, where the difference between peace and a state of non-peace (which I hope you agree is far broader that the presence of war) is hard to define. In fact, it will probably take several posts to get through definitions, and we might have some give and take over those definitions. For now, I'll leave you one of the best data sources for conflicts around the world, the Uppsala Conflict Database Project (UCDP), which has information on virtually every conflict since 1946 in the world. Please take a look at it at http://www.ucdp.uu.se/gpdatabase/search.php . By the way Uppsala is an elite Swedish University (and city), which devotes a great amount of it's resources to peace studies.
In my next post, I hope to give you an illustration of what I'm talking about, by using a hypothetical example of organizing a peace organization in a US congressional district. Hopefully, my illustration will clarify the way I propose to organize the peace process.
Thanks for reading, and please don't hesitate to comment.
Tuesday, March 20, 2012
Tuesday, March 13, 2012
Immanuel Kant's Revolution
Immanuel Kant's Revolution
An essay by Bill McKenna ©2012
First, let me apologize for my two week absence. My schedule has been disrupted as I’ve found
teaching work. The bad news is that I’ve
been forced to radically change my personal habit of being a ‘night owl’ to
being a ‘morning person’. I have been in
the habit of writing late at night, so the change has not been kind to my
output. On the other hand, I feel that
teaching is a major component of my purpose in life, so I am grateful for the
opportunity, even at the entry level, to practice this art. That’s enough of the personal, so let us
resume the peace work.
Today we’re going to tackle Immanuel Kant finally, so settle
down for a rather long read, with a rather important conclusion. This will wrap up my first foray into
philosophy; subsequent posts in the near future will return us to the 21st
century, and some practical thought.
Before I talk about Kant, I need to do some table
setting. I want to build a bridge
between Augustine and Kant, and Anselm of Canterbury is a convenient
bridge. Anselm concerned himself with
theoretical proofs of God. I find his
conclusions somewhat unremarkable, but his process was genius. His proof was a series of interlocking
arguments, the most important of which is the line of reasoning that if we
agree on the quality of something that is good (used in the sense of morality
in this case, not quality), then there must be a standard of goodness by which
we judge, and therefore, it follows, there must be an absolute good. If the universe contains an absolute good, it
is an intentional universe, and if it is intentional, there must be a God who
intended it. Please do not judge Anselm
by my quick synopsis. His proof is far
deeper than I need to take you. If you
wish to offer a critique of Anselm, you must study him further.
Anselm’s process is what is important here, as he makes a
case for an absolute good. To do so, he
relies on an a posteriori construct,
beginning from the point he is proving, and analyzing deductively. Thus, we know God exists because there is an
absolute good. Later, Kant will critique
Anselm on this line of thinking, but it is in his critique of Anselm’s elegant
logic that Kant’s a priori arguments flourish.
So, even though we find Anselm and Kant at logical loggerheads (and a six
hundred year gap), Kant will effectively use Anselm as a starting point.
Now we can discuss Kant.
Kant was a product of the European enlightenment, and was concerned that
the great thinkers of his time, such as Sir Isaac Newton, might posit that all human
understanding could eventually be induced by scientific thought and reason. Nonetheless, Kant was an enlightenment
master, and instead of opposing the whole concept of scientific thought, he
claimed that where reason would not suffice to answer the great questions,
philosophical thought was necessary. In
his Critique of Pure Reason (Kritik
der reinen Vernunft), Kant
asserted that in cases where the critical method failed to provide an answer it
was possible to accept a hypothesis from a practical point of view, relying on
an a priori set of knowledge (a
reversal of Anselm). In this argument,
Kant asserts that reason itself in built from a priori concepts, such as the innate knowledge of simple arithmetic
to build the science of mathematics.
Hence, in matters of morality, one can build a moral philosophy based on
the a priori presence of God. If we
cannot accept an a priori construct
we cannot reason beyond the refutation of the concept.
Nearly every western metaphysical philosopher since Kant has
relied on Kant’s theories as a base.
When I return to philosophical essays in the future, visiting Hegel or
the Concord Transcendentalists, you will see the ghost of Immanuel Kant.
Kant’s moral philosophy is difficult to work with. I remember lectures in college on Kant, and
thinking, ‘please let me absorb enough of this to pass the exam.’ At the time, I thought it was because Kant
was deadly boring, but now with a few years of maturity (now there’s a double euphemism),
I realize that Kant is just difficult, and not boring at all. In the hands of skilled debaters, the dispute
of a priori knowledge of God between
an atheistic perspective and a theological perspective would leave me, and many
of my readers, far back in the intellectual wake. Happily, I’m not leading you to that debate.
In 1795, based on his moral philosophy constructs, Kant
wrote an essay titled “Perpetual Peace:
A Philosophical Sketch”. He
relies on the a priori concept, that some things ought to be done transcending
human understanding, and that achieving universal peace is one of the most
important. His elegant reasoning then
gives way to a practical plan for universal peace, containing six preliminary
articles and three definitive articles1:
Preliminary articles:
- "No
secret treaty of peace shall be held valid in which there is tacitly
reserved matter for a future war"
- "No
independent states, large or small, shall come under the dominion of
another state by inheritance, exchange, purchase, or donation"
- "Standing
armies shall in time be totally abolished"
- "National
debts shall not be contracted with a view to the external friction of
states"
- "No
state shall by force interfere with the constitution or government of
another state"
- "No
state shall, during war, permit such acts of hostility which would make
mutual confidence in the subsequent peace impossible: such are the
employment of assassins (percussores), poisoners (venefici), breach of
capitulation, and incitement to treason (perduellio) in the opposing
state"
Definitive articles:
- "The
civil constitution of every state should be republican"
- "The
law of nations shall be founded on a federation of free states"
- "The
law of world citizenship shall be limited to conditions of universal
hospitality"
So, finally, there it is, in possibly actionable
format. If Augustine’s just war was the
best accommodation we might have made prior to Kant (yes, I’ll allow for the
possibility of other schema), here is a way forward. Now we can move forward. We can move beyond philosophy and start to
look at a blueprint for peace. My tongue
is not in my cheek, and it is not hyperbole.
This is it.
Naturally, it isn’t all good news. There’s a lot to do in these nine
articles. There are more than a few
scenarios that are hard to fit into the framework. Lastly, it is only philosophy, and can only
help if it is acted upon.
Some of what Kant says, however is very good news. Moreover, I want to add to that good
news.
Since Kant wrote his essay, humanity has endured terrible
warfare. Kant himself had to endure the
Napoleonic Wars in Europe. The twentieth
century was especially bloody. Yet
through it all, we are starting to apply some of Kant’s tents. The adoption has been slow and incomplete, but
where and when employed, they work. When
you get to his three definitive articles, you see that the republican form of
government is now the most common form of government. It has tended to make nations more peaceful,
and the democratic peace theory is an offshoot of the first article. Sadly, the increased popularity of the
republican form of government has revealed that many republics are nothing more
than covers from authoritarian rule, but evolutionary improvement in suffrage
appears to be moving humanity in the right direction. The second article concerning a law of
nations is also encouraging. For all of
its faults, the United Nations has successfully navigated difficult waters to achieve
a degree of authority of the collected nations of the world. You might correctly suppose that that will
probably be the subject of future essays.
The final article, universal hospitality, is harder to see, but progress
has been made there as well. The
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted by the United Nations in 1948,
has been perhaps the most important advance in this area.
Of course, we still have dictators, standing armies,
covert operations, and all manner of pre-Kantian behavior in our world
today. If we didn’t, perhaps I’d be
building model railroads instead of writing about this. We are, however, moving in the right
direction, and our slow march toward perpetual peace is unstoppable. As a student of history, it is clear to me
that humanity is evolving, not just in better civilization and governance, but
in a profound individual way. We are
becoming a more highly developed species.
We have a lot of work to do, my fellow friends and
peacemakers. Now that you know where I’m
coming from, let’s put our philosophers back in the closet for a while and let
them collect dust again. It’s time to
talk about practical matters.
Peace.
1 articles copied from Wikipedia article"Perpetual Peace"
Friday, March 2, 2012
Why have a social contract
Why have a social contract?
An essay by Bill McKenna ©2012
Before I take a giant leap into the European enlightenment,
let’s recap Augustine’s just war. I
could have been harsher in my treatment of the concept. It could be seen as a compromise between the
teachings of Christ and pragmatism. I think
that Augustine is better than that though.
He is making an argument that given moral sovereign authority to stop
evil war wagers by the use of force which will prevent suffering is just. The practical offshoot of applying such a
system really is a problem. Tying just
war to papal infallibility in medieval Western Europe, and you get the
crusades (edit - see comment section - papal infallibiliity was not a medieval dogma - example is still worth noting however). The Reformation brought the
Thirty Years’ War which was fought over the proper sovereignty within the
Christian Church itself. Every combatant
in that struggle claimed to be defending faith against those who would destroy
that faith. Lastly, the concept relies
on benevolent monarchs, presumably made sovereign through the grace of God. The idea of an insurrection or capricious
tyrants doing evil within their sovereign space is left unaddressed.
Just war philosophy was tremendously lacking, but it was
also revolutionary. I’ll give Augustine
full credit in western civilization for the revolution, but someone more
learned than I can speak to similar philosophies that arose in Indian and
Chinese culture. My point is, before
Augustine and his like-minded eastern philosophers, warfare was unlimited
except by strength of arms. After
Augustine, there is a moral value to peace.
It is an enormous step forward in civilization. Now, I ask you, what would the next step be?
Let’s jump more than 1,000 years ahead to England in the
1600’s. If you’ve learned Western Civ in
high school or college you may remember Thomas Hobbes as the foil for John Locke. I’ll briefly recap here. Both Hobbes and Locke developed an Enlightenment
period concept of a social contract, one of the founding concepts of political
science. Both philosophers argued that
in order to live more fulfilling lives as individuals, it is necessary to
create a social contract between a governing sovereign, and a governed
people. In other words, it is desirable
to surrender some portion of one’s own autonomy to accept the governance of a
recognized authority.
For Hobbes, in his book The Leviathan, man in a
natural state is beset by self-interest, and everyone living in this state of
nature is subject to the whims of the strongest. The pre-governed natural world of Hobbes
leads to lives that are “nasty, brutish, and short”. The way to develop a social contract is to
ordain an absolute authority. The
Hobbesian perspective of humanity in a natural state is that it is essentially
driven by base, evil objective thought.
John Locke, a near contemporary of Hobbes also advocated a social
contract, but his presumptions of human nature led him to an entirely different
outcome. In his Essay Concerning
Human Understanding, Locke talked about ‘natural law’ which governs how we
conduct our lives in the absence of absolute authority. In his view the social contract emerges from
our natural law, and we create government to codify and create private
property. The authority of the
government belongs to the governed.
Locke, therefore sees the natural human state as good, so that
government can be agreed upon by consent.
The Hobbes-Locke duality is a common subject for political
scientists, and it plays an important role in my thesis about peace. I will argue that civilization has evolved
over time; if one goes back to my Greek or Roman examples from last month, we
see remnants of the old ‘strongest empire model’ where large armed groups
preyed on the smaller. Over time,
however, as sovereignty has moved from kings and emperors to representative
government, we see that more emphasis is placed on the legal standing of
individuals and their rights. Clearly,
with current examples such as the barbarous suppression in Syria, we have a
long way to go before we emerge as a truly evolved civilization. Nonetheless, if you can allow me my thesis as
I develop it further, you will see that peace becomes inevitable, and we
collectively have the ability to hasten its arrival.
My long-winded thesis development is starting to take shape
now. If you’ve been reading along I hope
it’s holding together for you. Please
comment if you have any issue with it so far.
Immanuel Kant is up next, and then we can put our philosophers on the
back burner for a while, and move from peace theories to some practical stuff
for my peacemaking friends.
Peace to you all. I
need to get some sleep now, as I hope to attend the Sunrise Interfaith service
at Hampton Beach, which will involve (I think) The New England Peace Pagoda, NH
and MA Peace Action and the Friends Service Committee, hoping that my Buddhist
and Quaker brethren can use some prayers from a good Episcopalian. If freezing rain keeps me away, they may
expect my spiritual support at least.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)